Combinatory logic
Combinatory logic is a notation to eliminate the need for quantified variables in mathematical logic. It was introduced by Moses Schönfinkel[1] and Haskell Curry,[2] and has more recently been used in computer science as a theoretical model of computation and also as a basis for the design of functional programming languages. It is based on combinators, which were introduced by Schönfinkel in 1920 with the idea of providing an analogous way to build up functions—and to remove any mention of variables—particularly in predicate logic. A combinator is a higher-order function that uses only function application and earlier defined combinators to define a result from its arguments.
In mathematics
Combinatory logic was originally intended as a 'pre-logic' that would clarify the role of quantified variables in logic, essentially by eliminating them. Another way of eliminating quantified variables is Quine's predicate functor logic. While the expressive power of combinatory logic typically exceeds that of first-order logic, the expressive power of predicate functor logic is identical to that of first order logic (Quine 1960, 1966, 1976).
The original inventor of combinatory logic, Moses Schönfinkel, published nothing on combinatory logic after his original 1924 paper. Haskell Curry rediscovered the combinators while working as an instructor at Princeton University in late 1927.[3] In the late 1930s, Alonzo Church and his students at Princeton invented a rival formalism for functional abstraction, the lambda calculus, which proved more popular than combinatory logic. The upshot of these historical contingencies was that until theoretical computer science began taking an interest in combinatory logic in the 1960s and 1970s, nearly all work on the subject was by Haskell Curry and his students, or by Robert Feys in Belgium. Curry and Feys (1958), and Curry et al. (1972) survey the early history of combinatory logic. For a more modern treatment of combinatory logic and the lambda calculus together, see the book by Barendregt,[4] which reviews the models Dana Scott devised for combinatory logic in the 1960s and 1970s.
In computing
In computer science, combinatory logic is used as a simplified model of computation, used in computability theory and proof theory. Despite its simplicity, combinatory logic captures many essential features of computation.
Combinatory logic can be viewed as a variant of the lambda calculus, in which lambda expressions (representing functional abstraction) are replaced by a limited set of combinators, primitive functions without free variables. It is easy to transform lambda expressions into combinator expressions, and combinator reduction is much simpler than lambda reduction. Hence combinatory logic has been used to model some non-strict functional programming languages and hardware. The purest form of this view is the programming language Unlambda, whose sole primitives are the S and K combinators augmented with character input/output. Although not a practical programming language, Unlambda is of some theoretical interest.
Combinatory logic can be given a variety of interpretations. Many early papers by Curry showed how to translate axiom sets for conventional logic into combinatory logic equations.[5] Dana Scott in the 1960s and 1970s showed how to marry model theory and combinatory logic.
Summary of lambda calculus
Lambda calculus is concerned with objects called lambda-terms, which can be represented by the following three forms of strings:
-
-
-
where is a variable name drawn from a predefined infinite set of variable names, and and are lambda-terms.
Terms of the form are called abstractions. The variable v is called the formal parameter of the abstraction, and is the body of the abstraction. The term represents the function which, applied to an argument, binds the formal parameter v to the argument and then computes the resulting value of — that is, it returns , with every occurrence of v replaced by the argument.
Terms of the form are called applications. Applications model function invocation or execution: the function represented by is to be invoked, with as its argument, and the result is computed. If (sometimes called the applicand) is an abstraction, the term may be reduced: , the argument, may be substituted into the body of in place of the formal parameter of , and the result is a new lambda term which is equivalent to the old one. If a lambda term contains no subterms of the form then it cannot be reduced, and is said to be in normal form.
The expression represents the result of taking the term E and replacing all free occurrences of v in it with a. Thus we write
-
By convention, we take as shorthand for (i.e., application is left associative).
The motivation for this definition of reduction is that it captures the essential behavior of all mathematical functions. For example, consider the function that computes the square of a number. We might write
- The square of x is
(Using "" to indicate multiplication.) x here is the formal parameter of the function. To evaluate the square for a particular argument, say 3, we insert it into the definition in place of the formal parameter:
- The square of 3 is
To evaluate the resulting expression , we would have to resort to our knowledge of multiplication and the number 3. Since any computation is simply a composition of the evaluation of suitable functions on suitable primitive arguments, this simple substitution principle suffices to capture the essential mechanism of computation. Moreover, in lambda calculus, notions such as '3' and '' can be represented without any need for externally defined primitive operators or constants. It is possible to identify terms in lambda calculus, which, when suitably interpreted, behave like the number 3 and like the multiplication operator, q.v. Church encoding.
Lambda calculus is known to be computationally equivalent in power to many other plausible models for computation (including Turing machines); that is, any calculation that can be accomplished in any of these other models can be expressed in lambda calculus, and vice versa. According to the Church–Turing thesis, both models can express any possible computation.
It is perhaps surprising that lambda-calculus can represent any conceivable computation using only the simple notions of function abstraction and application based on simple textual substitution of terms for variables. But even more remarkable is that abstraction is not even required. Combinatory logic is a model of computation equivalent to lambda calculus, but without abstraction. The advantage of this is that evaluating expressions in lambda calculus is quite complicated because the semantics of substitution must be specified with great care to avoid variable capture problems. In contrast, evaluating expressions in combinatory logic is much simpler, because there is no notion of substitution.
Combinatory calculi
Since abstraction is the only way to manufacture functions in the lambda calculus, something must replace it in the combinatory calculus. Instead of abstraction, combinatory calculus provides a limited set of primitive functions out of which other functions may be built.
Combinatory terms
A combinatory term has one of the following forms:
Syntax | Name | Description |
---|---|---|
x | Variable | A character or string representing a combinatory term. |
P | Primitive function | One of the combinator symbols I, K, S. |
(M N) | Application | Applying a function to an argument. M and N are combinatory terms. |
The primitive functions are combinators, or functions that, when seen as lambda terms, contain no free variables.
To shorten the notations, a general convention is that , or even , denotes the term . This is the same general convention (left-associativity) as for multiple application in lambda calculus.
Reduction in combinatory logic
In combinatory logic, each primitive combinator comes with a reduction rule of the form
- (P x1 ... xn) = E
where E is a term mentioning only variables from the set {x1 ... xn}. It is in this way that primitive combinators behave as functions.
Examples of combinators
The simplest example of a combinator is I, the identity combinator, defined by
- (I x) = x
for all terms x. Another simple combinator is K, which manufactures constant functions: (K x) is the function which, for any argument, returns x, so we say
- ((K x) y) = x
for all terms x and y. Or, following the convention for multiple application,
- (K x y) = x
A third combinator is S, which is a generalized version of application:
- (S x y z) = (x z (y z))
S applies x to y after first substituting z into each of them. Or put another way, x is applied to y inside the environment z.
Given S and K, I itself is unnecessary, since it can be built from the other two:
- ((S K K) x)
- = (S K K x)
- = (K x (K x))
- = x
for any term x. Note that although ((S K K) x) = (I x) for any x, (S K K) itself is not equal to I. We say the terms are extensionally equal. Extensional equality captures the mathematical notion of the equality of functions: that two functions are equal if they always produce the same results for the same arguments. In contrast, the terms themselves, together with the reduction of primitive combinators, capture the notion of intensional equality of functions: that two functions are equal only if they have identical implementations up to the expansion of primitive combinators. There are many ways to implement an identity function; (S K K) and I are among these ways. (S K S) is yet another. We will use the word equivalent to indicate extensional equality, reserving equal for identical combinatorial terms.
A more interesting combinator is the fixed point combinator or Y combinator, which can be used to implement recursion.
Completeness of the S-K basis
S and K can be composed to produce combinators that are extensionally equal to any lambda term, and therefore, by Church's thesis, to any computable function whatsoever. The proof is to present a transformation, T[ ], which converts an arbitrary lambda term into an equivalent combinator.
T[ ] may be defined as follows:
- T[x] ⇒ x
- T[(E₁ E₂)] ⇒ (T[E₁] T[E₂])
- T[λx.E] ⇒ (K T[E]) (if x does not occur free in E)
- T[λx.x] ⇒ I
- T[λx.λy.E] ⇒ T[λx.T[λy.E]] (if x occurs free in E)
- T[λx.(E₁ E₂)] ⇒ (S T[λx.E₁] T[λx.E₂]) (if x occurs free in E₁ or E₂)
Note that T[ ] as given is not a well-typed mathematical function, but rather a term rewriter: Although it eventually yields a combinator, the transformation may generate intermediary expressions that are neither lambda terms nor combinators, via rule (5).
This process is also known as abstraction elimination. This definition is exhaustive: any lambda expression will be subject to exactly one of these rules (see Summary of lambda calculus above).
It is related to the process of bracket abstraction, which takes an expression E built from variables and application and produces a combinator expression [x]E in which the variable x is not free, such that [x]E x = E holds. A very simple algorithm for bracket abstraction is defined by induction on the structure of expressions as follows:[6]
- [x]y := K y
- [x]x := I
- [x](E₁ E₂) := S([x]E₁)([x]E₂)
Bracket abstraction induces a translation from lambda terms to combinator expressions, by interpreting lambda-abstractions using the bracket abstraction algorithm.
Conversion of a lambda term to an equivalent combinatorial term
For example, we will convert the lambda term λx.λy.(y x) to a combinatorial term:
- T[λx.λy.(y x)]
- = T[λx.T[λy.(y x)]] (by 5)
- = T[λx.(S T[λy.y] T[λy.x])] (by 6)
- = T[λx.(S I T[λy.x])] (by 4)
- = T[λx.(S I (K T[x]))] (by 3)
- = T[λx.(S I (K x))] (by 1)
- = (S T[λx.(S I)] T[λx.(K x)]) (by 6)
- = (S (K (S I)) T[λx.(K x)]) (by 3)
- = (S (K (S I)) (S T[λx.K] T[λx.x])) (by 6)
- = (S (K (S I)) (S (K K) T[λx.x])) (by 3)
- = (S (K (S I)) (S (K K) I)) (by 4)
If we apply this combinatorial term to any two terms x and y (by feeding them in a queue-like fashion into the combinator 'from the right'), it reduces as follows:
- (S (K (S I)) (S (K K) I) x y)
- = (K (S I) x (S (K K) I x) y)
- = (S I (S (K K) I x) y)
- = (I y (S (K K) I x y))
- = (y (S (K K) I x y))
- = (y (K K x (I x) y))
- = (y (K (I x) y))
- = (y (I x))
- = (y x)
The combinatory representation, (S (K (S I)) (S (K K) I)) is much longer than the representation as a lambda term, λx.λy.(y x). This is typical. In general, the T[ ] construction may expand a lambda term of length n to a combinatorial term of length Θ(n3).[7]
Explanation of the T[ ] transformation
The T[ ] transformation is motivated by a desire to eliminate abstraction. Two special cases, rules 3 and 4, are trivial: λx.x is clearly equivalent to I, and λx.E is clearly equivalent to (K T[E]) if x does not appear free in E.
The first two rules are also simple: Variables convert to themselves, and applications, which are allowed in combinatory terms, are converted to combinators simply by converting the applicand and the argument to combinators.
It is rules 5 and 6 that are of interest. Rule 5 simply says that to convert a complex abstraction to a combinator, we must first convert its body to a combinator, and then eliminate the abstraction. Rule 6 actually eliminates the abstraction.
λx.(E₁ E₂) is a function which takes an argument, say a, and substitutes it into the lambda term (E₁ E₂) in place of x, yielding (E₁ E₂)[x : = a]. But substituting a into (E₁ E₂) in place of x is just the same as substituting it into both E₁ and E₂, so
- (E₁ E₂)[x := a] = (E₁[x := a] E₂[x := a])
- (λx.(E₁ E₂) a) = ((λx.E₁ a) (λx.E₂ a))
- = (S λx.E₁ λx.E₂ a)
- = ((S λx.E₁ λx.E₂) a)
By extensional equality,
- λx.(E₁ E₂) = (S λx.E₁ λx.E₂)
Therefore, to find a combinator equivalent to λx.(E₁ E₂), it is sufficient to find a combinator equivalent to (S λx.E₁ λx.E₂), and
- (S T[λx.E₁] T[λx.E₂])
evidently fits the bill. E₁ and E₂ each contain strictly fewer applications than (E₁ E₂), so the recursion must terminate in a lambda term with no applications at all—either a variable, or a term of the form λx.E.
Simplifications of the transformation
η-reduction
The combinators generated by the T[ ] transformation can be made smaller if we take into account the η-reduction rule:
- T[λx.(E x)] = T[E] (if x is not free in E)
λx.(E x) is the function which takes an argument, x, and applies the function E to it; this is extensionally equal to the function E itself. It is therefore sufficient to convert E to combinatorial form.
Taking this simplification into account, the example above becomes:
- T[λx.λy.(y x)]
- = ...
- = (S (K (S I)) T[λx.(K x)])
- = (S (K (S I)) K) (by η-reduction)
This combinator is equivalent to the earlier, longer one:
- (S (K (S I)) K x y)
- = (K (S I) x (K x) y)
- = (S I (K x) y)
- = (I y (K x y))
- = (y (K x y))
- = (y x)
Similarly, the original version of the T[ ] transformation transformed the identity function λf.λx.(f x) into (S (S (K S) (S (K K) I)) (K I)). With the η-reduction rule, λf.λx.(f x) is transformed into I.
One-point basis
There are one-point bases from which every combinator can be composed extensionally equal to any lambda term. The simplest example of such a basis is {X} where:
- X ≡ λx.((xS)K)
It is not difficult to verify that:
- X (X (X X)) =β K and
- X (X (X (X X))) =β S.
Since {K, S} is a basis, it follows that {X} is a basis too. The Iota programming language uses X as its sole combinator.
Another simple example of a one-point basis is:
- X' ≡ λx.(x K S K) with
- (X' X') X' =β K and
- X' (X' X') =β S
In fact, there exist infinitely many such bases.[8]
Combinators B, C
In addition to S and K, Schönfinkel (1924) included two combinators which are now called B and C, with the following reductions:
- (C f g x) = ((f x) g)
- (B f g x) = (f (g x))
He also explains how they in turn can be expressed using only S and K:
- B = (S (K S) K)
- C = (S (S (K (S (K S) K)) S) (K K))
These combinators are extremely useful when translating predicate logic or lambda calculus into combinator expressions. They were also used by Curry, and much later by David Turner, whose name has been associated with their computational use. Using them, we can extend the rules for the transformation as follows:
- T[x] ⇒ x
- T[(E₁ E₂)] ⇒ (T[E₁] T[E₂])
- T[λx.E] ⇒ (K T[E]) (if x is not free in E)
- T[λx.x] ⇒ I
- T[λx.λy.E] ⇒ T[λx.T[λy.E]] (if x is free in E)
- T[λx.(E₁ E₂)] ⇒ (S T[λx.E₁] T[λx.E₂]) (if x is free in both E₁ and E₂)
- T[λx.(E₁ E₂)] ⇒ (C T[λx.E₁] T[E₂]) (if x is free in E₁ but not E₂)
- T[λx.(E₁ E₂)] ⇒ (B T[E₁] T[λx.E₂]) (if x is free in E₂ but not E₁)
Using B and C combinators, the transformation of λx.λy.(y x) looks like this:
- T[λx.λy.(y x)]
- = T[λx.T[λy.(y x)]]
- = T[λx.(C T[λy.y] x)] (by rule 7)
- = T[λx.(C I x)]
- = (C I) (η-reduction)
- (traditional canonical notation: )
- (traditional canonical notation: )
And indeed, (C I x y) does reduce to (y x):
- (C I x y)
- = (I y x)
- = (y x)
The motivation here is that B and C are limited versions of S. Whereas S takes a value and substitutes it into both the applicand and its argument before performing the application, C performs the substitution only in the applicand, and B only in the argument.
The modern names for the combinators come from Haskell Curry's doctoral thesis of 1930 (see B, C, K, W System). In Schönfinkel's original paper, what we now call S, K, I, B and C were called S, C, I, Z, and T respectively.
The reduction in combinator size that results from the new transformation rules can also be achieved without introducing B and C, as demonstrated in Section 3.2 of Tromp (2008).
CLK versus CLI calculus
A distinction must be made between the CLK as described in this article and the CLI calculus. The distinction corresponds to that between the λK and the λI calculus. Unlike the λK calculus, the λI calculus restricts abstractions to:
- λx.E where x has at least one free occurrence in E.
As a consequence, combinator K is not present in the λI calculus nor in the CLI calculus. The constants of CLI are: I, B, C and S, which form a basis from which all CLI terms can be composed (modulo equality). Every λI term can be converted into an equal CLI combinator according to rules similar to those presented above for the conversion of λK terms into CLK combinators. See chapter 9 in Barendregt (1984).
Reverse conversion
The conversion L[ ] from combinatorial terms to lambda terms is trivial:
- L[I] = λx.x
- L[K] = λx.λy.x
- L[C] = λx.λy.λz.(x z y)
- L[B] = λx.λy.λz.(x (y z))
- L[S] = λx.λy.λz.(x z (y z))
- L[(E₁ E₂)] = (L[E₁] L[E₂])
Note, however, that this transformation is not the inverse transformation of any of the versions of T[ ] that we have seen.
Undecidability of combinatorial calculus
A normal form is any combinatory term in which the primitive combinators that occur, if any, are not applied to enough arguments to be simplified. It is undecidable whether a general combinatory term has a normal form; whether two combinatory terms are equivalent, etc. This can be shown in a similar way as for the corresponding problems for lambda terms.
Undefinability by predicates
The undecidable problems above (equivalence, existence of normal form, etc.) take as input syntactic representations of terms under a suitable encoding (e.g., Church encoding). One may also consider a toy trivial computation model where we "compute" properties of terms by means of combinators applied directly to the terms themselves as arguments, rather than to their syntactic representations. More precisely, let a predicate be a combinator that, when applied, returns either T or F (where T and F represent the conventional Church encodings of true and false, λx.λy.x and λx.λy.y, transformed into combinatory logic; the combinatory versions have T = K and F = (K I)). A predicate N is nontrivial if there are two arguments A and B such that N A = T and N B = F. A combinator N is complete if NM has a normal form for every argument M. An analogue of Rice's theorem for this toy model then says that every complete predicate is trivial. The proof of this theorem is rather simple.[9]
By reductio ad absurdum. Suppose there is a complete non trivial predicate, say N. Because N is supposed to be non trivial there are combinators A and B such that
- (N A) = T and
- (N B) = F.
- Define NEGATION ≡ λx.(if (N x) then B else A) ≡ λx.((N x) B A)
- Define ABSURDUM ≡ (Y NEGATION)
Fixed point theorem gives: ABSURDUM = (NEGATION ABSURDUM), for
- ABSURDUM ≡ (Y NEGATION) = (NEGATION (Y NEGATION)) ≡ (NEGATION ABSURDUM).
Because N is supposed to be complete either:
- (N ABSURDUM) = F or
- (N ABSURDUM) = T
- Case 1: F = (N ABSURDUM) = N (NEGATION ABSURDUM) = (N A) = T, a contradiction.
- Case 2: T = (N ABSURDUM) = N (NEGATION ABSURDUM) = (N B) = F, again a contradiction.
Hence (N ABSURDUM) is neither T nor F, which contradicts the presupposition that N would be a complete non trivial predicate. Q.E.D.
From this undefinability theorem it immediately follows that there is no complete predicate that can discriminate between terms that have a normal form and terms that do not have a normal form. It also follows that there is no complete predicate, say EQUAL, such that:
- (EQUAL A B) = T if A = B and
- (EQUAL A B) = F if A ≠ B.
If EQUAL would exist, then for all A, λx.(EQUAL x A) would have to be a complete non trivial predicate.
However, note that it also immediately follows from this undefinability theorem that many properties of terms that are obviously decidable are not definable by complete predicates either: e.g., there is no predicate that could tell whether the first primitive function letter occurring in a term is a K. This shows that definability by predicates is a not a reasonable model of decidability.
Applications
Compilation of functional languages
David Turner used his combinators to implement the SASL programming language.
Kenneth E. Iverson used primitives based on Curry's combinators in his J programming language, a successor to APL. This enabled what Iverson called tacit programming, that is, programming in functional expressions containing no variables, along with powerful tools for working with such programs. It turns out that tacit programming is possible in any APL-like language with user-defined operators.[10]
Logic
The Curry–Howard isomorphism implies a connection between logic and programming: every proof of a theorem of intuitionistic logic corresponds to a reduction of a typed lambda term, and conversely. Moreover, theorems can be identified with function type signatures. Specifically, a typed combinatory logic corresponds to a Hilbert system in proof theory.
The K and S combinators correspond to the axioms
- AK: A → (B → A),
- AS: (A → (B → C)) → ((A → B) → (A → C)),
and function application corresponds to the detachment (modus ponens) rule
- MP: from A and A → B infer B.
The calculus consisting of AK, AS, and MP is complete for the implicational fragment of the intuitionistic logic, which can be seen as follows. Consider the set W of all deductively closed sets of formulas, ordered by inclusion. Then is an intuitionistic Kripke frame, and we define a model in this frame by
This definition obeys the conditions on satisfaction of →: on one hand, if , and is such that and , then by modus ponens. On the other hand, if , then by the deduction theorem, thus the deductive closure of is an element such that , , and .
Let A be any formula which is not provable in the calculus. Then A does not belong to the deductive closure X of the empty set, thus , and A is not intuitionistically valid.
See also
- Applicative computing systems
- B, C, K, W system
- Categorical abstract machine
- Combinatory categorial grammar
- Explicit substitution
- Fixed point combinator
- Graph reduction machine
- Lambda calculus and Cylindric algebra, other approaches to modelling quantification and eliminating variables
- SKI combinator calculus
- Supercombinator
- To Mock a Mockingbird
References
- ^ Schönfinkel 1924, The article that founded combinatory logic. English translation: Schönfinkel (1967).
- ^ Curry 1930.
- ^ Seldin 2008.
- ^ Barendregt 1984.
- ^ Hindley & Meredith 1990.
- ^ Turner 1979.
- ^ Lachowski 2018.
- ^ Goldberg 2004.
- ^ Engeler 1995.
- ^ Cherlin 1991.
Literature
- Barendregt, Hendrik Pieter (1984). The Lambda Calculus, Its Syntax and Semantics. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. Vol. 103. North Holland. ISBN 0-444-87508-5.
- Cherlin, Edward (1991). "Pure functions in APL and J". Proceedings of the international conference on APL '91 - APL '91. pp. 88–93. doi:10.1145/114054.114065. ISBN 0897914414. S2CID 25802202.
- Curry, Haskell Brooks (1930). "Grundlagen der Kombinatorischen Logik" [Foundations of combinatorial logic]. American Journal of Mathematics (in German). 52 (3). The Johns Hopkins University Press: 509–536. doi:10.2307/2370619. JSTOR 2370619.
- Curry, Haskell Brooks; Feys, Robert (1958). Combinatory Logic. Vol. I. Amsterdam: North Holland. ISBN 0-7204-2208-6.
- Curry, Haskell Brooks; Hindley, J. Roger; Seldin, Jonathan P. (1972). Combinatory Logic. Vol. II. Amsterdam: North Holland. ISBN 0-7204-2208-6.
- Engeler, E. (1995). The Combinatory Programme (PDF). Birkhäuser. pp. 5–6.
- Field, Anthony J.; Harrison, Peter G. (1998). Functional Programming. Addison-Wesley. ISBN 0-201-19249-7.
- Goldberg, Mayer (2004). "A construction of one-point bases in extended lambda calculi". Information Processing Letters. 89 (6): 281–286. doi:10.1016/j.ipl.2003.12.005.
- Hindley, J. Roger; Meredith, David (1990). "Principal type-schemes and condensed detachment". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 55 (1): 90–105. doi:10.2307/2274956. JSTOR 2274956. MR 1043546. S2CID 6930576.
- Hindley, J. Roger; Seldin, Jonathan P. (2008) [1986]. Lambda-Calculus and Combinators: An Introduction (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521898850.
- Lachowski, Łukasz (2018). "On the Complexity of the Standard Translation of Lambda Calculus into Combinatory Logic". Reports on Mathematical Logic. 2018 (53): 19–42. doi:10.4467/20842589RM.18.002.8835. Retrieved 9 September 2018.
- Paulson, Lawrence C. (1995). Foundations of Functional Programming. University of Cambridge.
- Quine, Willard Van Orman (1960). "Variables explained away". Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. 104 (3): 343–347. JSTOR 985250.
Reprinted as Chapter 23 of Quine (1996)
- Quine, Willard Van Orman (1996) [1960]. "Variables explained away". Selected Logic Papers (Enl. ed., 2. print ed.). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. pp. 227–235. ISBN 9780674798373.
- Schönfinkel, Moses (1924). "Über die Bausteine der mathematischen Logik" (PDF). Mathematische Annalen (in German). 92 (3–4): 305–316. doi:10.1007/bf01448013. S2CID 118507515.
The article that founded combinatory logic. English translation: Schönfinkel (1967)
- Schönfinkel, Moses (1967) [1924]. Van Heijenoort, Jean (ed.). Über die Bausteine der mathematischen Logik [On the building blocks of mathematical logic]. From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931. Translated by Bauer-Mengelberg, Stefan. Cambridge, MA, USA: Harvard University Press. pp. 355–366. ISBN 978-0674324497. OCLC 503886453.
- Seldin, Jonathan P. (3 March 2008). "The Logic of Curry and Church" (PDF). Retrieved 17 September 2023.
- Smullyan, Raymond (1985). To Mock a Mockingbird And Other Logic Puzzles Including an Amazing Adventure in Combinatory Logic. Knopf. ISBN 0-394-53491-3.
A gentle introduction to combinatory logic, presented as a series of recreational puzzles using bird watching metaphors.
- Smullyan, Raymond (1994). Diagonalization and Self-Reference. Oxford logic guides. Vol. 27. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0198534501.
Chapters 17–20 are a more formal introduction to combinatory logic, with a special emphasis on fixed point results.
- Sørensen, Morten Heine B; Urzyczyn, Paweł (2006) [1999]. Lectures on the Curry–Howard Isomorphism (PDF). Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. Vol. 149 (1st ed.). Elsevier. p. 442. ISBN 978-0444520777. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2005-10-16. Retrieved 2017-04-22.
- Tromp, John (2008). "Binary Lambda Calculus and Combinatory Logic" (PDF). In Calude, Cristian S. (ed.). Randomness And Complexity, from Leibniz To Chaitin. World Scientific Publishing Company. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-03-04.
- Turner, David A. (1979). "Another Algorithm for Bracket Abstraction". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 44 (2): 267–270. doi:10.2307/2273733. JSTOR 2273733. S2CID 35835482.
- Wolfengagen, V. E. (2003). Combinatory logic in programming: Computations with objects through examples and exercises (2nd ed.). Moscow: "Center JurInfoR" Ltd. ISBN 5-89158-101-9.
- Wolfram, Stephen (2021). Combinators: A Centennial View. Wolfram Media. ISBN 978-1-57955-043-1.
A celebration of the development of combinators, a hundred years after they were introduced by Schönfinkel (1924)
(eBook: ISBN 978-1-57955-044-8)
External links
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: "Combinatory Logic" by Katalin Bimbó.
- 1920–1931 Curry's block notes.
- Keenan, David C. (2001) "To Dissect a Mockingbird: A Graphical Notation for the Lambda Calculus with Animated Reduction."
- Rathman, Chris, "Combinator Birds." A table distilling much of the essence of Smullyan (1985).
- Drag 'n' Drop Combinators. (Java Applet)
- Binary Lambda Calculus and Combinatory Logic.
- Combinatory logic reduction web server
- Wolfram, Stephen (29 April 2020). Combinators: 100-Year Celebration. Wolfram Physics Project on YouTube. Retrieved 26 September 2023.
See what we do next...
OR
By submitting your email or phone number, you're giving mschf permission to send you email and/or recurring marketing texts. Data rates may apply. Text stop to cancel, help for help.
Success: You're subscribed now !